1. Race typology argued for homogenous groupings of individuals ("types"), and emphasized the variation between rather than within them. Deviations were explained as the product of mixture, so for example 19th century typologists argued blonde-haired Australian aborigines were the result of interbreeding with Europeans, and narrow-nosed Horner Africans were the result of mixture with "Caucasoids", both claims have been shown to be false... Marks says: "Again, the point of the theory of race was to discover [large] clusters of people that are principally homogeneous within and heterogeneous between, contrasting groups." If you cannot show this, you aren't talking about race...
I am relocating, so my replies might be delayed a bit.
When it comes to race, the historiography is generally pretty awful. It's improving, though, so if you are relying on secondary sources try more recent ones, for example:
Doron, C. O. (2011). Races et dégénérescence. L'émergence des savoirs sur l'homme anormal.
Doron, C. O. (2012). Race and Genealogy: Buffon and the Formation of the Concept of „Race‟.
Generally, it's better to look at the primary sources, which is what I did.
But yes, Dobzhansky, Relethford, Marks, and Hochman have all made easily demonstrable mistakes. (On request, I will enumerate them.) Regarding Dobzhansky, for example, he initially characterized Kant as something of a typologist; he changed his position by 1970:
To make this diversity manageable, pioneer anthropologists assumed that at some time in the past there existed several homogeneous, or "pure," races, each with a certain complex of morphological, and perhaps also psychological, traits. The modern diversity of humans is then ascribed to mixing of these basic racial types in various combinations and proportions. For example, Kant (1775) assumed four primary races: white, negro, Hunnic (Mongolian), and Hindu, and stated that it is "possible to derive from these four races all other hereditary ethnic characters, either as mixed or as incipient races . . . " (quoted from Count, 1950) (HUMAN DIVERSITY AND ADAPTATION, 1950).
[quote]Immanuel Kant, who was a naturalist before he became the prince of philosophy, wrote in 1775 the following remarkably perceptive lines.
It appears that Kant had a clearer idea about the distinction between individual variability ad the variability of population than many authors writing today. (Genetics of the Evolutionary Process, 1970)
3. The fact 19th century scientists once thought races were species demonstrates what I have been saying: races were seen to be vastly different. This is the opposite what we know today, and what you are arguing for (trivial/low amounts of genetic variation between groups).
I actually discussed this issue quite a bit. Since you seem to be uninterested in reading what I wrote, I will just quote a section:
By this narrative, once-upon-a-time races were thought to represent "real natural kinds," but it turned out that there were no such kinds and so mainstream scientists later rejected the concept. In actuality, close to the opposite occurred, at least insofar as we are referring to intraspecific divisions.
Let us clarify this latter point, first. As noted in section II, in context to natural history, the term “race” was used both exclusively to refer to a sort of intraspecific division and inclusively to refer to this in addition to species. The latter usage allowed for the question: “Are the races of man species?” Insofar as race was used to describe intraspecific variation it referred to “constant varieties,” genealogically understood. In the 20th century, the indiscriminate concept of varieties was retired and terms such as “polymorph” and “race” were employed to describe different sorts of intraspecific variation. “Race” gained an exclusively intraspecific denotation – though, outside of the natural sciences it was and is still often used in the inclusive sense, for example, when people refer to the “human race” and mean the “human species” or when fantasy fiction novels speak of different separately created races such as the elves and dwarves of Middle Earth. Since the term “race” had this dual meaning there is a sense in which some scholars believed that the races of man were natural kinds in the species realist sense – after all, some believed that races were species and that species were separate creations. Thus one has to interrogate the specific meaning of the claims. Smith (2013) makes it clear that he is speaking about races as “subdivision of the human species,” so we will frame our discussion in terms of this understanding.
For a more lengthy discussion try my section II-B "Semantic Complexities and the Evolution of the Race Concept".
Generally, Buffon, Blumenbach, Kant, and Duchesne developed a concept which they called "race" which described "constant varieties" understood genealogically. Polygenists, though, argued that the term "race" should be more generally applied. Thus, in reply to Kant, Georg Forster noted:
We have borrowed <the term> [race] from the French; it seems very closely related to <the words> racine and radix and signifies descent in general, though in an indeterminate way. For one talks in French of the race of Caesar <in> the same <way> as of the races of horses and dogs, irrespective of the first origin, but, nevertheless, as it seems, always with tacit subordination under the concept of a species... <The word> should mean nothing more than a mass of men whose common formation is distinctive and sufficiently at variance with their neighbors <such that they> could not be immediately derived from them. <They are> a lineage whose derivation is unknown, and consequently, one which we cannot easily count under one of the commonly accepted human varieties because we lack knowledge of the intermediary link.
Race, the term, then ended up referring to two concepts: (a) (exclusive) genealogically understood contant varieties and (b) (inclusive) genealogically understood contant varieties plus genealogically understood species. Only by the latter concept would some "races" -- the ones which were thought of as being species -- have been thought of in a typological manner (as you mean it). Since (b) includes (a), though, even if you wanted to equivocally argue that "races" were thought typologically (adopting concept b), you would have to admit that they also were not. As a result, even equivocation can not rhetorically save the argument. Do you disagree on this point?
4.[/b] Dobzhansky's focus was local populations, and not "Caucasoids" and "Mongoloids" etc. You can search for these terms on Google Books to see they rarely appear in his work: "Negroid" only appears 3 times in Mankind Evolving (and one of these is when he is quoting someone else), "Caucasoid" only appears once.
Dobzhansky made it quite clear that his concept scaled up. See the attached. Below are more example:
"The human species is compounded of numerous subordinate Mendelian populations, which form an intricate hierarchy, beginning with clans, tribes, and various economic and cultural isolates, and culminating in "major" races, and finally the species... Now, not only the major but also the minor populations differ in gene frequencies. They are "races" by definition...One must, however, be on guard not to invent a "population" by hand-picking a "group" of individuals who do not belong to a common gene pool. For example, people with O blood group, or long-haired people, or criminals are not Mendelian populations and can not reasonably be called races....The characteristic Mongoloid facial structure may be an example of "climatic engineering" which gives the greatest protection to cold and windy climates." (Race and Humanity)
"The five "races" of Blumenbach were:
...
This was a biological classification which obviously described existing differences between large populations inhibiting different parts of the world." (Heredity, Race and Society)
"Discrepancies between the "genetic" and the "taxonomic" species are to be expected mainly in those relatively rare cases where different groups do not interbreed despite the scarcity or absence of morphological differences between them (a good example of this sort are the "races"o f Trichogrammam inutum described by Harland and Atteck), or where geographically isolated races, without losing the ability to interbreed, have diverged so widely in their morphological characters that taxonomists feel compelled to consider them separate species (for instance, some "species" of pheasants." (A Critique of the Species Concept in Biology)
"The fossil Grimaldi people in southern France were like some Negroids now living in Africa..." (Evolving Mankind)
"Thus, the gene Rho is rare among whites but con~-non among Negroes, while Rhl is relatively rare among Negroes and common among whites and especially among Mongoloids." (HUMAN DIVERSITY AND ADAPTATION)
"Only one thing is certain -- the populations of Europe and Africa were not identical with those of Java and China. The human species was then, as it is now, differentiated into geographic races....All the branches but one withered and became extinct; the sole surviving branch is the present Homo sapiens. This branch has, in turn, split into diverging twigs -- the present human races." (ON SPECIES AND RACES OF LIVING AND FOSSIL MAN)
................
Interestingly, in "Heredity, Race and Society", Dobzhansky also states:
"One of the greatest absurdities of the so called race problem in the United states is that anyone who admits having some African ancestry is classed as a Negro regardless of his or her appearance. A "Negro" is then a member of a social and economic group rather than of a purely biological one[/b]. Some of the children born of such "Negroes" are indistinguishable from, and, "pass" among the whites in order to avoid anti-Negro discrimination."
"African Americans" surely represent a "breeding population which differs on average from "European Americans". If your and Gannet's interpretation is correct, why does Dobzhansky feel that it's absurd to consider "Negroes" to be a biological group? He does say that his races are "biological units", so why aren't Negroes one of these? However, if I am correct, why are "economic and cultural isolates" races? Is an "isolate" different from a "group"?
Anyways, you said:
5. Only Garn's "micro races" = demes. He had a hierarchy of populations. The largest were "geographical races" such as continents, but these were not demes (panmictic populations). That is why the hierarchy makes no sense
.
I don't think that Garn equated races with demes -- but I will have to read more of his articles to be sure. That is, I imagine that his races were like Dobzhansky's where while all races are "Mendelian populations", not all Mendelian populations -- specifically demes which were not genetically "distinct" -- are races. Thus, he notes that his races share a fraction of genes in common. Strictly speaking demes do not need to. Would not you agree?
They aren't pigeon-holing people. Pointing out someone's ancestors came from Oceania, or Sub-Saharan Africa is not a classification, it is just a description. Sauer (1992) covers this in detail, i.e. to identify someone as having ancestry from Northern Europe, does not mean they are a "Nordic race".
When you assign someone to a biogeographical
group based on their ancestry, you are "pigeon-holing" (i.e., classifying) them no different than when you assign them to a "race" the same way. But I agree that one need not classify (group); one could just describe ancestry components -- and some researchers do this. If you want specific examples in which individuals are arranged into divisions I can give them. But you say:
Instead you claim it is "silly" and wrong, when the truth is your concept and redefinition of race is what is "silly" (it trivializes race, so what is the point?) and wrong (it is not a defence of the traditional race concept).
I discussed this above.
Please refer me to the said people who in a typological manner divided the human species into races. Provide specific references so that I can read the papers.
Now, on that note, a clarification is necessary. Contrary to what you have implied, I do not adopt a "population" understanding of race -- indeed, I criticize these because I find them vague and ill-defined. The more I read Dobzhansky the more compelling I find my critique. Instead of a population understanding, I adopt a cluster class one, one which is perfectly consistent with Darwin's and mostly consistent with Blumenbach's and Buffon's. (It differs from Kant's class understanding in that it is a cluster ones, not a character essential class concept.) I do note, though, that "genetic population" and cluster concepts such as Hartl and Clark's are no different. Whether Dobzhansky's is depends on what exactly he meant by "genetically distinct" Mendelian populations.
So, your criticism of Dobzhansky's "re-definition" does not constitute a criticism of the concept I presented.